Modern philosophical ethics has
been dominated by two general positions: utilitarianism and deontology (Kantian
ethics). According to the first, the
just or right thing to do is the thing that is most useful to the most
people. So it is right to tell the truth
most of the time because general honesty has good social consequences. However, it might be right to lie in special
circumstances. If a suicidal young man
asks where his gun is, telling him the truth might be the morally worst thing
to do.
According to deontology or duty
based ethics, an act is moral only if you do it because it is the right thing
to do. Telling a lie is wrong because it
manipulates another human being, thus treating him as subhuman or as a mere
means to an end. Deontologists will
generally say that you must do the right thing regardless of the consequences
to yourself or others. Kant narrowed
down the meaning of “the right thing to do” with his two categorical
(unbending) imperatives: act so that the principle of your action can be
universalized and act always to treat other human beings as person to be served
and never as means to be exploited.
Utilitarianism and deontology
are usually present as mutually exclusive.
Oddly, most people switch (if unconsciously) between the two positions
in different situations. The best
example of this is the infamous trolley problem. The trolley problem comes in two
versions.
Version 1A trolley is headed toward a switch. As the switch is set, the trolley will go left and as a result will kill five people who are working (or tied to) the track. You can leave the switch as is or switch it to the right track. In that case it will kill a single person on the track.
Version 2You are standing on a bridge next to an obese person, watch the train approach. If it passes under the bridge it will kill five people on the track. You can save them only by pushing the large guy onto the track, thus resulting in his death.
Most people (and almost all of
my students) who are presented with the first version choose to throw the
switch. They defend their decision on
the grounds that it is morally better to sacrifice one person to save
five. That is textbook utilitarian
thinking.
Results tend to change
dramatically when people are presented with the second version. Most people refuse to push the fellow over on
the grounds that one is deliberating killing him in order to stop a train. That is textbook deontology.
The key to understanding the
two positions is to see that they focus on distinct aspects of a potentially
moral action. The utilitarian focuses on
the consequences of the action. The
deontologist focuses on the motive of the moral actor. What I find most interesting is that you can
defend both positions using the assumptions of the other. While deontology is much less flexible than
utilitarians would like, it seems pretty clear that society would be a lot
better off if everyone acted (almost) all the time from deontological
principles. There would be no crime and dilemmas
which force one to choose between motives and consequences would be much rarer.
Likewise, a Kantian might
employ utilitarian principles as good candidates for universalization. He might say that anyone in the situation of
the first version problem should throw the switch, regardless of who was on the
track, because saving five rather than one is the universally right thing to
do. However, it would be all but
impossible to throw the fat guy over without violating the second categorical
imperative.
Virtue ethics has recently been
revived as a third position. According
to this, what is important in morality is the dynamic relationship between acts
and character. By doing what is right
consistently, as a matter of principle, one builds the habit of acting morally. When one has such habits, one will of course
tend to do the right thing for the right reason. Virtues may be said to be such habits, but I
think it more correct to say that virtue is precisely the dynamism involving
actions and character. Brave actions
produce bravery which produces brave actions; that is what makes courage a virtue.
It seems pretty clear that
morality has deep roots in evolution. Cooperators
are frequently more successful in a Darwinian sense (reproductive success) than
non-cooperators and so cooperation can be selected for. In many cases in the history of animals,
situations arise where cooperation involves the temptation to cheat. Some mechanisms must be found for denying
reproductive success to cheaters; otherwise, cooperative instincts will be
selected out of the gene pool.
To take one famous example,
vampire bats frequently share blood with one another. This provides insurance for those who have
string of bad hunting days. The bats
have rather large brains, in part perhaps to remember who shares and who does
not. Cheaters are excluded from the
social safety net. It is not that the
bats understand what they are doing. It
is rather that moral principles are built into their behavioral schemas.
Human beings are consummate cooperators. We cooperate with extended nets of partners
and have natural expectations regarding their behaviors. We are sensitive to others opinions of us,
especially concerning our fitness as honest partners. We are naturally inclined to be angry when we
suppose that another is not observing his or her obligations.
Cooperation is obviously
utilitarian from a “gene’s eye” point of view.
Human societies have inherited the earth. However, cooperative societies are also the
conditions of the good human life. Our interests are dependent upon but not
at all identical with the persistence of our genes.
It seems obvious that morality
is in part utilitarian. We need for one
another to behave morally. It seems to
me just as likely that Kantian elements have been selected for in the evolution
of our moral psychology. A person who is
uncomfortable with doing the wrong thing is obviously a better candidate for a
cooperative partnership. He or she makes
a better business partner, friend and ally, or spouse.
Just as morality cannot be
reduced to evolutionary mechanisms (though it must be supported by them) it
cannot be reduced merely to making us useful to one another. This is where virtue ethics is most
helpful. Such Aristotelian virtues as
courage, temperance, honesty, and righteous indignation are socially beneficial
to be sure. They are also beneficial to
the virtuous person. To the extent that
an individual possesses virtue, he or she is more likely to take advantage of
good fortune and bear up under bad fortune.
The virtuous person is most fit for the best human life.
In the Politics Aristotle expressed his non-reductive thinking with this
immortal phrase: though the polis (the political community) comes to be for the
sake of mere life, it is exists for the sake of the good life. He was distinguishing here the historical
forces responsible for the emergence of political life from the value of
political life for human beings.
I suppose that while the moral
dimension in human psychology came to be for the sake of mere reproductive
success, it exists for the sake of our success.
Morality rests on evolutionary foundations. It enables the formation of societies that
are good to live in, in ways that utilitarianism and deontology shed light
on. It is also important to forming an
individual character worth having. The
latter confirms the Platonic/Aristotelian account of the virtues.
No comments:
Post a Comment