In chapter 2 of Intelligent
Virtue, Julia Annas explains two
things. One is that virtue is a reliable
disposition of a person to perform virtuous actions. This disposition must be cultivated. A person is encouraged toward virtuous
actions by her parents and her friends and associates. She may consciously cultivate virtue in
herself. It is by doing virtuous things
that one develops a virtuous character.
To acquire a virtue is to become a certain kind of person, which is to
say, a person who tends to do virtuous things.
Virtue does not arise
abstractly, as if we decide in advance which actions are virtuous and then
attempt to motivate people to do such actions.
Rather, virtue is developed by working on and with existing motivations,
encouraging and shaping the ones that tend toward virtue and discouraging those
that do not.
She confronts a certain chicken
and egg problem here. If virtuous
actions and virtues seem to produce one another, is one nonetheless primary
over the other? You might suspect that
we value a virtuous character only for the sake of virtuous actions, and so the
latter are primary. Annas objects. To employ a famous analogy which she does not
employ, it like the saying that if you give someone a fish he eats for a day
but if you teach him to fish he eats for life.
Just as knowing how to fish is more valuable than any single fish, a
virtuous person is more valuable than any single virtuous action.
I would add a couple of
reflections at this point. One concerns
the classical view of beauty. The
beautiful makes it possible to appreciate virtue apart from the outcome of
virtuous actions. If we value virtue
only for the sake of virtuous actions, and virtuous actions for the sake of the
good things that they make possible, then we would value virtue only when it is
successful. Yet it is quite possible,
perhaps unavoidable, to admire virtue when it cannot succeed. We admire the three hundred Spartans even
though they perished and their bravery had no significant strategic value. That is because it was beautiful.
A second reflection concerns
the biological roots of virtue. Annas acknowledges
the existence or at least the possible existence of natural virtues. We may be born with at least some tendency
toward virtue. Though he doesn’t use the
same terms, Michael
Tomasello’s excellent book Why We
Cooperate? is addressed precisely to this question. Here is a quote from a post at my old blog South
Dakota Politics:
Chimpanzees are capable of
cooperating but they lack any understanding of cooperation. Two chimps can each learn to pull a bar in
sequence, so that food is delivered. But
all each chimp knows is that if I
pull the bar, I get the food. Neither chimp understands that the other has
to do his part, nor does either expect, let alone demand, that the other
cooperates.
Human children, from an early
age, have a sense of “we-ness”. Helping
behavior, unlearned and not signaled, develops spontaneously. When a child (about 3 years old) sees an
adult in need of assistance (say, opening a cabinet door), the child is moved
to provide it. In one fascinating
experiment, an adult plays a simple game with a child. The child puts a block in one of two inclined
tubes. It slides down the tube and the
adult catches it in a tin can. It makes
a pleasant ring and the adult shouts in satisfaction. The game is obviously fun, so when the adult
walks away the child will try to bring him back to the game. The child understands that the adult is a
partner whom he needs to keep playing, that the game is something that “we” are
doing. This is something that
chimpanzees cannot grasp.
I submit that this is evidence for natural virtue. Young children spontaneously develop a sense
of mutual obligations. That is what we
work on when we attempt to cultivate virtue in our children and in
ourselves.
The second thing that Annas explains in this chapter is virtue
is not about routines. A routine is
something we develop so we can perform some task without devoting much thought
to it. Annas uses the example of driving
every day to a certain location. It
becomes a routine when we always use the same route and do it so unreflectively
that we often are barely aware of getting there.
Virtuous action may indeed be quicker than thought. Annas uses the analogy of the master piano
player, who can translate his understanding of a piece of music into the work
of his fingers very fast. Unlike a
routine, however, this work is essentially intelligent. He has a conception of the work, what it
means and how it ought to be played. He
is intensely aware of what he is doing. He
can do it well because he has cultivated his genius over a long period of
time. Like the ace tennis player, he
responds creatively to every moment.
Annas employs an important point made by Aristotle. Courage is most evident in those who respond
to unexpected situations. Those who rely
on routines are at a loss when a sudden alarm or something else unforeseen calls
for a creative response. Someone with
the virtue of courage can respond more effectively to such surprises precisely
because her virtue was developed in a long series of creative responses (dare I
say, adapting) to circumstances as they arise.
No comments:
Post a Comment