An ethical concept is thin to
the extent that it narrowly describes an action, as for example: the right
thing to do is the thing that maximizes utility or satisfies the categorical
imperative or is in accord with the commands of God. It is intended to work regardless of what assumptions
we make about the world and the persons that act morally in that world.
An ethical concept is thick to
the degree that it includes descriptive elements about the context of the
action, based on shared notions about people and the nature of human
existence. Hiding Jews from Nazis was
the right thing to do because it was the brave thing to do, knowing what we
know about the peril faced by the persecuted and their defenders.
In Chapter 3 of Intelligent
Virtue, Julia Annas defends the
thickness of virtue ethics. Her best
point employs the skill analogy against thin ethical theories. Such theories demand “right-making
characteristics” that have to be present in all right actions. The best example would be in Kantian
ethics. An action is right if and only
if it is done because it is right. Okay,
but which actions should be done because they are right?
To answer that question, Kant
deploys his two versions of the categorical imperative: a right action is one
based on universal principles and it is one that treats human beings as ends
and never as means. Okay again, but do
these principles tell us what to do when the Nazis show up at my front
door? Maybe, but it isn’t clear. Should I universalize the principle that everyone
should always tell the truth or the principle that everyone should protect the
innocent against the evil?
Annas considers the case of
learning Italian. Is there some
principle that all grammatically correct Italian sentences must comply
with? Or is it rather the case that you
have to know whether it is a statement or a question or an exhortation, who is
speaking to whom, whether it is about the past, present or the future? To know the correct way to speak in any
actual case it is necessary to have thick concepts of grammatical correctness. You need to understand tenses, moods, parts
of sentences, etc.
Likewise with moral actions,
you need to know how to act in a range of contexts that vary widely in ways
that will resist reduction to any simple formulation. To decide whether I should lie to the Nazis
about the Jews hiding in my basement, I need to know something about bravery in
particular. To be truly virtuous, I have
to have the dispositions and understand to act bravely (and creatively) in a
range of situations. I am more likely to
act calmly and effectively if I am fluent in the virtue in question.
To add to Annas’ reflections,
the development of virtue, like mastering a language or learning to play the
piano, depends on a considerable number of evolved dispositions and
capacities. It is not reducible to those
products of evolution because it must be developed creatively in response to unforeseeable
circumstances. Virtue is as much a
product of that development as it is of the basic evolutionary legacies.
It seems clear to me that the thick
concepts of virtue ethics are far more realistic and richly endowed than the
any thin, abstract approaches to ethics.
It is also the case that virtue ethics can be grounded in evolutionary
biology and so has the most solid foundation of all the modern theories.
No comments:
Post a Comment