What follows is the beginning of a paper I will present in Vancouver next month.
We
few, we happy few, we band of brothers, for he today who sheds his blood with
me shall be my brother,
In the Politics [1252a ff.],
Aristotle presents us with an almost evolutionary account of the origin of
political communities. “If we look at
the growth of things from their beginning,” he tells us, we will be in the best
position to speculate about the nature of the political community. So, he begins with the most elementary human
community: that of man and women and their offspring and “that which by nature
can rule and that which by nature is to be ruled. The latter include beasts of burden, whether
human (slaves) or other animals. That he
includes the second association tells us that this is not an evolutionary
account, a point to which we shall return.
If we ignore the second
elementary community, we can easily make an evolutionary story out of Aristotle’s
account. Families, which serve everyday
needs come together into villages. The
most natural version of the latter is the enlarged clan. This is why the “first cities” were ruled by
kings and why human beings still imagine that the gods are so ruled, for the
rule of the king is the natural extension of the rule of the father. A union of villages comes next, which must
include a number of clans, and this larger group can achieve self-sufficiency. It is the polis, the political community, and
while it comes to be for the sake of living (meeting our biological needs), it
exists for the sake of the good life.
That last comment is vitally important, for it distinguishes the driving
force of evolution from the agenda that human beings can follow when their
basic biological needs are met with plenty.
Alone among living creatures, human beings get to decide what to do with
our time.
Until fairly recently,
evolutionary social theory followed the same lines as Aristotle. It was assumed that our ancestors first lived
together in small, extended families and that these come together in larger and
larger groups. In fact, it was probably
the other way around. When the Ur ancestors
of all the hominims first came down out of the trees, we did so in groups of
individuals who were not necessarily closely related. We came down in groups because group size was
the only defense we had against the predators which hunted on the ground. It is unlikely that anything like a family
existed yet, if we define family as both a mother and a father who together
invest in the rearing of their offspring.
This doesn’t mean that familial instincts were not a fundamental force
in social evolution or that Aristotle is wrong about the family as a template
for the emergence of political forms.
In this essay, I will argue that
the human family is both a cause and effect of our social evolution. You cannot have a human family as we
understand it without a larger community to support it, nor can you have the
emergence of the larger human communities, leading up to the political
community, without such families. As the
pre-human species explored the various routes to cooperation that natural
selection allowed, the potentially political larger community and the family
co-evolved.
No comments:
Post a Comment