This is an elaboration of the
second point I wish to make in my paper at the APSA this fall. As I stated in my previous post, to make
group selection work you need mechanisms that enable altruists to benefit each
other and to avoid being exploited. Otherwise,
altruists who work to benefit the group at their own expense will promote the
reproductive success of cheaters within the group. Since the cheaters pay none of the costs of
benefiting the group, they will proliferate at the expense of the altruists. I argue here that another evolutionary vector
for cooperative behavior can help to explain how this problem was solved.
Reciprocal altruism is one of the
basic explanations for cooperative behavior among organisms. Altruism is here defined in terms of a sacrifice
and a benefit, both measured in the coin of the probability of reproductive
success. When organism A delivers some
benefit to some other organism B, at some cost to A, because it is likely that the favor will be returned, that is
reciprocal altruism. I use the term because to indicate the selection
pressure that sustains the trait in both organisms.
A paradigmatic example is blood
sharing among vampire bats. These
nocturnal hunters must feed every three days to survive, leaving them at the
mercy of chance as the herds of animals they prey on move around. The bats manage the risk by a system of
sharing. If one comes back hungry, she
will cozy up to another who obviously sports a full belly. The latter will share some of her bounty
because this makes it more likely that the beneficiary will share later. There are many such examples in nature, but
almost all of them involves exchanges between individuals.
Christopher Boehm has argued in
two magnificent books (Hierarchy in the
Forest and Moral Origins) that human
social evolution was driven by a specific problem. Human beings have always been extraordinarily
good at cooperating with their fellows.
This, more than anything, explains why we have inherited the earth. Once we began to cooperate in hunting,
gathering, etc., a problem presented.
Some members of each group (free riders) were tempted to let everyone
else shoulder the burden (pay the cost in reproductive fitness) while taking
their share of the bounty. Another kind
of problem is the individual who, due to physical and perhaps psychological
advantage, was tempted to take more than his share of whatever was of
value. If these problems could not be
solved, the evolutionary emergence of cooperation would have been
precluded. The free riders and bullies
would have proliferated in the populations and the cooperators would have withered
until the social unit dissolved.
The way that this problem was
managed was group enforcement. Cheaters
were sanctioned by their comrades. Slackers
could easily be marginalized. Bullies
required more strenuous interventions; however, even the biggest primate cannot
stand up to the crowd and anyway, he is vulnerable while he is sleeping. Boehm proposes that group enforcement
eventually became psychologically internalized and that this is the
evolutionary origin of the moral sense in human beings.
It occurs to me that this account
is a special case of reciprocal altruism.
What is special about it is that the parties are not two individuals, as
in the paradigmatic cases, but the individual and the group. The individual sacrifices the temptation to
take more than his fair share. If
someone always has a bum leg when it is time for hunting or war he conserves
his energy and avoids risks, the better to invest them in reproductive
success. If he tries to push his weight
around, again, he is exploiting the group.
Every good citizen sacrifices such advantages to the political whole. The group in turn has to pay the costs of
enforcement, which may not be negligible if the bully is really big and the
slackers are more than a few. If the
group is successful, it becomes a powerful cooperative unit.
The social contract has long been
regarded as an abstract and artificial invention of philosophers. To the contrary, it seems to be an emergent
product of human evolutionary history. I
think that there are only two possible ways to make group selection work. One is if the groups frequently break up and
reassemble. Those groups with more
cooperators than not out compete those that chance to be pregnant with
cheaters. I suspect that such a process,
continually repeated, might result in the proliferation of altruists.
I suspect, however, that every genuine
case of group selection requires enforcement mechanisms. Cheating must be suppressed if cooperation is
to flourish. This is true even if the
cooperators are mostly related. There
are always black sheep in the family.
The evolution of politics is proof that the problem of group selection
can be solved.
No comments:
Post a Comment