In the paper I presented in
Vancouver, there were three new ideas.
They were new at least to me! One
is that kin selection is in fact group
selection: the target of selection in cases of inclusive fitness (I risk my
life to save three brothers) is clearly not me.
It is instead the genetic inheritance of my family.
The second is that in primate
groups and especially in our hunter-gather ancestral groups a very
sophisticated form of reciprocal altruism is presenting itself. When the group policies the behavior of the
individual members, a social contract is in force. The parties in this case are not two
individuals, as in one animal doing a favor for another when it is likely that
the other will return the favor. A group
that protects its members by sanctioning bullies and free riders is enforcing a social contract between the individual and
the group itself.
The third idea is that the once
the group protects each individual within it, one of the things that can be
protected is the access of each individual male to his mate. This is, effectively, the social construction of marriage. It seems likely that the nuclear family as we
understand it is a product of the emergent social contract. This is vital because, once it happens, the
group can recognize not only the bonds between couples within the group, but
bonds that extend beyond the group to the wife’s family.
Here I discuss the first idea. Early in Human
Evolutionary Psychology (Louise Barrett, Robin Dunbar, & John Lycett)
group selection is briefly considered and summarily rejected. It is only the fitness of individuals that
counts in natural selection. Almost
immediately the text complicates the matter by considering the selfish gene
argument. I will argue that it is
complicated in the other direction as well.
These are the basic models for
the evolution of cooperation. Kin
selection (or inclusive fitness) indicates cooperative behavior that is
selected for because it benefits closely related individuals. In the paradigmatic example, if I call out
because I see a tiger and so save the lives of five brothers, I may get more of
the genes that code for my familial sacrifice into the next generation than if
I survive and sire children of my own.
Reciprocal altruism indicates a
tradeoff: one individual pays a cost in order to benefit another because it is
likely that the cost will be returned.
When one vampire bat shares blood with another because the other be
expected to reciprocate later, that benefits both parties.
Group selection indicates
cooperation on the part of a member of the group that benefits the group but
not necessarily the altruist. Consider a
group of organisms bound together and living in a pond. When they run out of oxygen, the group must
rise to the surface. Producing the
substance that allows them to rise requires energy and thus involves a
sacrifice. The sacrifice only pays off
if enough individuals make the sacrifice to get the group where it needs to
go.
What occurred to me as I was
writing this paper is that in all these cases, the target of selection was more
than one individual. The term “target of
selection” indicates the actor whose behavior or trait was selected for. If a well-camouflaged insect avoids predators
and so successfully mates and reproduces, we can say that individual was the
target of selection.
In cases of group selection, the
group is by definition the target of selection.
It is the fitness of the group that is favored by natural selection; individual
members benefit only in so far as they are along for the ride.
The same is true, however, for
reciprocal altruism. Consider the case
of cleaner fish and their predatory clients.
The former consumes parasites off the skin and jaws of the latter. Each must give up something: the cleaners eat
only the parasites and not the healthy tissue; the predators refrain from
eating the cleaners. What is the target
of selection in this case? I submit that it is the alliance. Together they are selected for; divided they
are selected against.
In the case of kin selection, the
target is not the individual who calls out the warning, for she is more likely
than the others to attract the predator’s gaze.
Nor is the target of selection any individual sibling or cousin. According to Hamilton’s rule, cooperation
among kin can be selected for when c < rb.
Here c is the cost of the
cooperative act, measured in the probability of successful reproduction on the
part of the cooperator. If a certain
action is likely to result in reproductive failure one out of four times you do
it, then c = .25. If reproductive
failure is almost certain (I charge the lion to save my brothers and sisters) c
= close to one. How closely I am related to the individuals I am taking a
risk for is r. Siblings are .5. How many siblings I am saving is the benefit, or b.
This explains the paradigmatic
example deployed above. If I sacrifice
my life to save three brothers, then 1 < .5 x 3. What is key here is that the target of
selection, the T whose reproductive success is being selected for, is not any
individual. The target of selection is
the family.
Two things stand out for me. One is that kin selection seems to provide a
very limited selection pressure in organisms like ourselves (as opposed to social
wasps, bees, and ants). For siblings, r =
.5; but for cousins it is only 12.5.
Only if the clan were a very strong institution, so that such a sacrificial
act could reliably benefit a large number of relatives, would it be able to
work.
The other is that it runs into
some of the same problems that group selection models face. In the latter, the altruists in the group
enable the group to grow larger due to their sacrifices; however, non-altruists
in the group benefit more since they are making no sacrifices. Eventually, the cheaters will outnumber the
altruists and the system will collapse.
This is why many theorists suppose that group selection cannot
work. To make it work, you need
mechanisms that enable altruists to find each other and to exclude
cheaters.
Kin selection is supposed to be
more reliable because I can be more certain who my real siblings are and so my
sacrifice will promote the genes that code for my behavior. How reliable is this? Only once the family is institutionalized can
I have a good idea who my brothers and sisters are. If the nuclear family emerged first in the
course of human social evolution, and human beings were more rather than less
monogamous before they joined together in larger units, then kin selection
might have been the original driving force in that social evolution.
If, however, the family is the
product rather than the cause of our evolutionary trajectory towards political
animals, then kin selection is a much less significant (which is to say, not
insignificant) factor in that trajectory.
Aristotle was surely correct to say that human beings are more a
coupling than a political animal, since that is true of all sexually
reproducing vertebrates. Coupling,
however, does not mean “familial”. Kin
selection presupposes and therefore cannot explain the emergence of a coherent
family unit.
No comments:
Post a Comment