I just finished Robin Dunbar’s
magnificent book Human Evolution: Our
Brains and Behavior. Dunbar presents
two central hypotheses (if I understand the argument). One is that there is a
robust correlation between the brain size of primate species and the size of
the groups that they live in and interact with.
The causation that is indicated
by the correlation is it problematic for animals to live together. We annoy each other. Living in close proximity means that we can
come into conflict over a wide range of things: food, mates, space, etc. This annoyance has to be managed.
One way to manage it is by
grooming. When one baboon grooms another
(coming through the fur, looking for juicy insects that carry pathogens, it
results in the release of endorphins.
Endorphins play a large part in the book. Nothing makes it easier to tolerate the
presence of another furry conspecific than a warm fuzzy feeling that she
produces while she fondles my back.
It is easier, of course, to
tolerate others when the others are closely related. Kin selection is one of the foundational
theories in sociobiology. If one of my
inherited traits is to serve my offspring or my siblings, I am promoting the
biological success of individuals who, mostly, inherit the same traits.
The problem with both solutions
to the problem of group living is that they don’t allow for very large
groups. Kin selection works according to
Hamilton’s rule. If the cost of
cooperating with someone else is less than my relatedness to the other times
the benefit I bestow, then cooperation can be selected for. The formula can be stated simply: kin
sacrifice is selected for whenever C < RB.
For example, I am foraging with
my brother and I see a predator stalking us.
Should I call out a warning? The
answer is no. I am related to my brother
by a factor of point five. We share
fifty percent of the same genes. If my
brother survives, that is a factor of one.
If the tiger nails me because I called out a warning, that is a cost of
one: zero chance of future offspring. 1>.5
x 1. Hamilton’s rule is not
satisfied. Natural selection will not
favor this behavior because the genes that code for it will diminish in any
population.
What if I am foraging with seven
brothers when I see the cat? Now the
calculation reverses. My cost is still
one if I die and the relatedness is still point five. But the benefit (saving seven brothers) is
seven. 1 < .5 x 7. If my seven brothers survive and reproduce, I
get more of my genes into the next generation than if I have my own offspring. My nieces and nephews will inherit my
familial piety.
Kin selection is a robust
foundation for cooperation and it explains how closely related individuals can
work together. It is limited, however,
in its range. While brothers are related
by a factor of point five, cousins are related by a factor of point twelve and
a half. A willingness to take risks on
behalf of cousins will need a lot more cousins to make the calculation
work. Kin selection cannot explain the
emergence of communities much larger than the clan, let alone communities that
include unrelated clans.
Grooming can explain how
unrelated individuals learn to tolerate one another. It feels good to be groomed by another,
regardless of our relationship. This
works wonders for a lot of primate species.
Here, Dunbar deploys a second device: a time-budget model. There are only so many hour in a day. Some of these must be devoted to sleeping and
resting. More must be devoted to feeding
and moving from one source of food to another.
Some must be devoted to social bonding activities like grooming. Grooming involves two individuals and so only
so much of it can occupy the social bonding segment of the time budget.
The genius of Human Evolution
lies in the use of these two devices‑brain size vs. group size and the
time-budget model to map out the emergence of human beings as a branch of the
family tree. Our ancestors came together
in groups and the groups came together in larger groups. This enlargement of the social contract was
both a cause and a consequence of the enlargement of our mammalian brains. Laughter (we bond over jokes), language, alcohol,
and religion were the devices by which we solved the problems stated
above.
Why, for instance, did we survive
where the Neanderthals did not? Perhaps
because, by the time we encountered one another, we could muster much larger
coalitions of cooperative groups than they could.
No comments:
Post a Comment