I was interviewed today by David
Tucker, Senior Fellow at the Ashbrook Center at Ashland University. The interview will be posted soon and I
expect that it will be available to anyone (I didn’t exactly ask!). If so, I will post a link here.
Our topic was Darwin and the
Declaration. While I was preparing for
the interview, something occurred to me that might be worth further
thought. I am thinking it through here for
the first time.
One of the greatest innovations
in Aristotle’s writing concerned a way of confronting apparent paradoxes. A paradox occurs when something appears to be
two things at the same time and the two things are apparently
contradictory.
To take a simple example, consider
an oblong table not quite so wide than your hips and longer than the reach of
both arms. Standing at one end, it
appears narrower than you. Now walk
around it and look at it from its middle. From this point of view, it is wider than
you. That is the paradox: “narrower than
you” and “wider than you” are contradictory propositions. It can’t be both at the same time; and so,
the table is impossible. If this seems
silly, more intelligent people than you or I have been driven to distraction by
such things. The obvious solution (once
it occurs to you) is that the table is at least a two-dimensional object. Its multi-dimensionality allows it to be both
narrower and wider at the same time.
Using this kind of strategy,
Aristotle solved a wide range of problems in philosophy. How is it possible that a baby can be both
entirely material (the stuff of flesh) and also entirely formal (it’s a baby
and not just a lump of stuff)? Because
organisms (and indeed all lumps) have these two dimensions‑material and
form. To complete the explanation,
Aristotle added efficient cause (the baby is being pushed out of its initial
state by its phusis, or nature) and
it is growing toward maturity (the telos
or end of its growth).
Now consider a mature animal, say
a horse. How do we understand what this
is? On the one hand, it is one thing:
this here animal. “This here” is
frequent Aristotelian terminology; it points you toward the thing to be
examined. On the other hand, it is many
things: a head and a haunch, an outside with hide and eyeballs and an inside
with organs. We can keep searching down
to cells, subcellular devices, complex and simple molecules, etc. It is one thing and many at the same
time.
We can also go in the other
direction. The horse is one horse but
there are other horses. While it is one
thing, standing alone in the pasture, it is part of one larger thing: the
species Horse. And Horse
is one distinct thing and yet a part of a larger thing: Mammal, etc., etc.
Here is what occurred to me
today: horse and Horse are not
quite the same thing. To speak of a horse
is to say that this here animal is horsy.
It has traits that we recognize and that allow us to place it in a
larger category. To speak of Horse is to speak about something just
as real but rather larger: the collection of all the existing horses.
Aristotle got hung up on this,
and had a difficult time deciding whether horse or Horse was the real object of theoretical understanding. Much the same thing happened in the
philosophy of biology. Some have thought
that Horse is an individual,
bounded in space and time and therefore just as much an individual as the horse
I am riding on.
We have here a paradox. A species is something attributable to this
here animal; yet, it is also a larger thing and, more interestingly, a thing
that not only extends across space but also backwards in time. Biological classifications are categories,
conceptual boxes into which we place specimens; yet Horse is also a real object that occupies both local and
temporal space, back to the ancestor of all horses.
What is the real thing, the
individual animal or the species extending backward and forward (hopefully) in
time? The task of philosophy is to
explain how the answer can be yes.
No comments:
Post a Comment