Locke was closer to the truth
than Hobbes. That is not a surprising
sentiment coming from an American; even less so coming from an American
patriot. The United States is a Lockean
regime. It was founded on principles
derived explicitly from Locke’s political thought and more or less explicitly
on a rejection of Hobbes’ account of politics.
I would argue, however, that modern biopolitical research is backing up
John more than Thomas.
Both Hobbes and Locke began with
the early modern assumption that human beings are by nature individual animals
and that human society is largely an historical artifact. All our instincts, in so far as we have any,
are those of a creature as naturally asocial as a bear. Human social life is as artificial as umbrella:
it is something we cobbled together to meet our needs. This is a mistake. We were social long before we were genuinely
human.
Hobbes supposed that we were and
remain perfectly amoral and selfish in our motivations. What makes us dangerous to one another, when
we come together in social groups, is precisely that selfishness combined with
a distrust of one another. Government is
necessary to force us to suppress these selfish mutually hostile inclinations
and cooperate with one another.
Locke recognized that we also
possessed a sense of justice. When
someone transgresses on my rights I am offended. I am offended even when I observe some
transgressing against a third party in a case where my own interests are not
involved. It is this sense of righteous
indignation that makes us most dangerous to one another. We may pursue retribution beyond any selfish
interest and, if the perceived offender believes he is the one who has been
wronged, we become locked in a cycle of retribution. That is what necessitates the formation of
governments. Only by turning over such
disputes to an arbitrator can we resolve them without perpetual war.
This question, whether pure
selfishness is the motivation or whether there is a moral or proto-moral
motivation has been playing out in primate studies. I have been digesting a lot of research on
capuchin monkeys. Brown capuchins are “known
to engage in rich cooperative behaviors… and more consistently exhibit
other-regarding tendencies in donation tasks than chimpanzees.” That is, in experiments where one individual must
cooperate with another to reap a reward (food), capuchins seem more concerned
with what the other partner is getting or not getting.
In experiments modeled on the
ultimate game, the capuchin subject must decide whether to pull a lever that
will distribute food to herself and a conspecific partner. When the distribution is unequal-the subject
receives less food or a lower value food, the subject will often refuse the distribution. At first glance, the subject appears to be acting
out of sense of fairness. If I can’t get
what’s coming to me, then no one gets anything.
But is this right?
The subject may be motivated by
inequity aversion, a distaste for unfair distributions. Let us call that the Lockean motive. However, a lot of research indicates that the
real motive may be simple frustration.
The subject wants the greater share or the better reward and rejects the
distribution because of a frustrated desire.
Let us call that the Hobbesian motive.
Capuchin researchers have parted
along the Lockean/Hobbesian divide. Franz
de Waal and his associates began the argument with a series of studies that
pushed the Lockean interpretation. In
response, other researchers made the case for the Hobbesian-frustration
interpretation. I thought that the
balance was tilting against the Lockean side until today.
Kristin L. Leimgruber et. al.,
have a report in the journal Evolution
and Human Behavior [37 (2016) 236-244] that tells for the Lockean view: “Capuchin
monkeys punish those who have more.”
Here is the abstract:
Punishment of non-cooperators is important for the maintenance
of large-scale cooperation in humans, but relatively little is known about the
relationship between punishment and cooperation across phylogeny. The current
study examined second-party punishment behavior in a nonhuman primate species known
for its cooperative tendencies—the brown capuchin monkey (Cebus apella). We
found that capuchins consistently punished a conspecific partner who gained
possession of a food resource, regardless of whether the unequal distribution
of this resource was intentional on the part of the partner. A non-social
comparison confirmed that punishment behavior was not due to frustration, nor
did punishment stem from increased emotional arousal. Instead, punishment
behavior in capuchins appears to be decidedly social in nature, as monkeys only
pursued punitive actions when such actions directly decreased the welfare of a
recently endowed conspecific. This pattern of results is consistent with two
features central to human cooperation: spite and inequity aversion, suggesting
that the evolutionary origins of some human-like punitive tendencies may extend
even deeper than previously thought.
These findings present a
decidedly Lockean monkey. It isn’t just
that I, capuchin that I am, am not getting what I want. It’s that the other hairy fellow is getting
more, dammit.
Capuchin monkeys are more
distantly related to John Locke than chimpanzees. Spite and inequity aversion are part of our
emotional pallet that go beyond self-interest.
A purely selfish individual doesn’t care what others get; she only cares
what she gets. An animal who is
genuinely offended when a distribution is unfair is a moral animal.
I think it is clear that human
beings are Lockean animals. If capuchin
monkeys are as well, that suggests that morality is older than we are. As the trajectory of evolution pushed into
primate design space, it opened up the dimension of genuine moral
consciousness.
No comments:
Post a Comment