One of the great problems with
contemporary debates over free will is that two distinct and fundamental
philosophical questions are frequently (almost always) confused. One is the question whether the ubiquitous
human intuition of an open future is metaphysically viable. Do I really have choices that are not already
made yet, in the sense of being predetermined by the state of the Kosmos before
I make the choice? The second is whether
human consciousness is part of the chain of causation leading to human
actions. Did I drop the hot object
because it hurt? Or was my conscious pain
merely an epiphenomenon, generated by the underlying physical processes but
having no consequences of its own?
This has been a persistent
concern of mine for some years. Tonight
I have been reading Eckart Voland’s interesting article: “We Recognize Ourselves as Being Similar to
Others: Implications of the “Social Brain Hypothesis” for the Biological
Evolution of the Intuition of Freedom.”
Voland clearly regards our intuition of freedom as an illusion and sets
out to explain how we came by it. His
thesis is that it is a byproduct of modeling the intentions of other
persons. Here is a bit from the
abstract:
If, as the “social brain hypothesis” alleges, the main
selective pressure among primates is on generating social knowledge about one’s
cooperators and competitors, then it is the knowledge about others and not the
knowledge about oneself that is the scarce cognitive resource. It is beneficial
to make the others predictable and to form hypotheses about their probable
behavioral tendencies. This is done by behavior reading and mind reading and by
classifying the recurring stochastic patterns in everyday language as the
“will.” Thus, the idea of free will emerged first as a social attribution and
not as an introspectively gained insight.
I strongly suspect that Voland
is right on the specific question. It
seems to me more than likely that the human sense of self and of deliberation
(and particularly moral deliberation) emerged in tandem with a “theory of mind,”
which is to say, a recognition that other persons have minds like “mine”. However, I do not see how this thesis is
required, let alone advanced, either by determinism or epiphenomenalism.
Here is how Voland begins his
essay:
The human psyche, with its ability to feel, think, and act,
is a deterministic system. In the current discussion, this thesis is primarily
supported by arguments informed by neurobiology.
I have long regarded
determinism as one of the myths of modern science. The problem with all myths is not that they
are false but that they cannot be verified and that the reason for believing in
them has nothing to do with their veracity.
It may well be that the state of the Kosmos at any moment, T1,
rigidly determines the state of K at T2. How one could know that is beyond me, and it
is not a necessary assumption for any science.
All the scientist needs to suppose is that T1 determines some
part of T2 within some specified margin of error.
I will pass here on the
question of why so many want to believe in something that is unverifiable and
unnecessary. I will point out that when
Voland speaks of neurobiology, he has in mind certain findings that indicate
that the brain makes up its mind before the mind becomes conscious of making a
decision. Again, this may be true;
however, it is an argument not for determinism but for epiphenomenalism.
Voland makes a pitch for the
proposition that genuine freedom cannot have evolved.
Contrary to other claims: Freedom does not evolve, and what
is more: Freedom could not evolve, because if we assume that organisms which
could make use of the freedom to not obey the biological imperative were created
by a whim of nature, then natural selection would disfavor these genotypes to
the degree that they were to make use of this freedom, and the endless game of
evolution would proceed without them. Freedom here is understood in the sense
of the indeterministic libertarian intuition of being able to behave in other
ways, if one only wanted to do so.
To prevent a widespread misunderstanding: The antithesis of
determination is indetermination and not flexibility. Humans, perhaps like no
other species, are capable of special behavioral flexibility, which in turn is
carried by special cognitive abilities designed for this purpose. This allows
humans, more than other organisms, to adequately deal with situations that are
new to them and to cope with unusual requirements (Kanazawa, 2004). This
changes nothing, however, with regard to the fact that all of the knowledge of
how requirements are to be mastered already must exist in the form of certain
strategies of perception and thinking in the organism, completely within the
meaning of Kant’s a priori (Heschl, 2001). There is no room in this
system for a libertarian freedom of the will, i. e. the capacity to act
differently under identical conditions and to cause behavior while oneself
being uncaused.
This strike me as altogether
wrong. “Flexibility” means precisely not obeying “the biological
imperative.” It means this in two
ways. One is that the biological,
preprogrammed imperative must be responsive to different situations. The organism must be able to zig and zag in
ways that cannot be fixed ahead of time.
The other is that organisms
that disobey “the biological imperative” may be the ones that flourish when the
environmental niche has changed.
Evolution has engineered a vast number of modes of flexibility. The most pervasive is genetic diversity, of
which, the most interesting is sexual reproduction. Is it not obvious that consciousness is
precisely the most sophisticated form of flexibility? Let us suppose that all conscious creatures
are capable of some measure of freedom, in the sense of making choices that are
not governed by deterministic rules. That
would allow such creatures to be very flexible in their responses to the
environment.
How then to keep such creatures
honest in a Darwinian sense? The obvious
answer is to bribe them. This is the function
of pain and pleasure, discontent and happiness.
Rather than giving precise instructions to sentient animals, evolution
was content to give them parameters. Do
whatever you want so long as you survive long enough to reproduce.
This is the only account, as it
seems to me, that explains why it hurts when I pick up something that is very hot. If consciousness is really an epiphenomenon,
produced by but not effecting biological processes, then it is a very odd phenomenon. It is analogous to the occasionalism that you
find in dualistic theories. It doesn’t
seem like a winner.
It is interesting how little this debate changes when religion is removed from the equation. Voland's pre-determinism doesn't dissimilar to Calvin's predestination.
ReplyDeleteBut Voland's comments and your responses remind me of an earlier post you made about bees. I objected to bee tyranny and the lack of freedom bees had. You explained that when bees rebelled it threatened the very existence of the hive. In the case of the bees, Voland's assumption seems to be right. Nature seems to select against freedom. You seem to suggest that this is not the case with humans - but at what point did humans or their ancestors become able to develop freedom without killing themselves off?
Miranda: I am grateful, as always for your comments. I apologize for the tardiness of this reply.
ReplyDeleteBees have relatively little freedom, to be sure; however, they are bees. We don't even know if they are conscious. Honey bee hives are astonishingly productive precisely because so many individuals are constrained by the laws of the tribe. However, they have to be constrained. The queen eats eggs that she does not produce, thus suppressing rebellion. In this case, yes, the reproductive interests of the worker females lies in the success of the queen and not in the success of their rebellious tendencies.
On the other hand, the hive requires that its laws have escape clauses. If too many foragers fail to return to the hive, workers mature early--violating a long standing rule.
I think that consciousness emerges in evolutionary history because it allows an unprecedented level of complexity in the face of unforeseeable circumstances. A tiger will poke and prod the first turtle it finds to see if it can be opened. If the species is maintain itself, conscious choice must be constrained to some degree. That is why we get hungry.
So I think that both freedom and constraint are selected for, in different measure in different species. We ought not to confuse the evolutionary origins of freedom from its value to us. There are evolutionary explanations for why I like single malt scotch; however, that isn't why I buy it. I buy it because it is further proof that God loves me and wants me to be happy.
Dr. Blanchard: Thank you very much for taking the time to respond. I am sorry for neglecting this blog for so long. Your reply makes perfect sense and I find myself without any more questions on this point. I particularly agree with your last point!
ReplyDeleteThank you, Miranda. We are indeed on agreement regarding that last point.
ReplyDelete