In Plato’s Euthyphro, Socrates arrives at the courthouse to face indictment
and encounters a young man who is there to sue his own father for the murder of
a hired hand. This is an astonishing act
in view of ordinary Greek morality. Murder
was conceived of as a crime against families.
The role of the court was to reconcile the families with some kind of
settlement. Euthyphro explains that he
is acting out of a piety that transcends familial obligation.
This setting is extraordinarily
informative. It gives us a sense of how
much distance some Greeks had achieved from their traditional, pagan moral
view. It also allows Socrates to cross
the stage as it were. In Aristophanes’ the
Clouds, Socrates’ teaching brought a
young man to assault his father. In the Euthyphro, he defends the father against
the son.
The question of the dialogue is
‘what is piety?’ Euthyphro’s first
answer is that piety is what the Gods love and impiety is what the God’s
hate. This quickly leads to a
difficulty, because Euthyphro accepts the traditional myths in which the Gods
quarrel. If they quarrel, Socrates
points out, then what one God loves another will not love and so the same thing
will be both pious and impious. Socrates
allows the two of them to paper over this problem with the revision that piety
is what all the Gods love and vice versa.
Then, however, Socrates asks a
cleaving question. He is my revised
version:
Suppose that some act is pious. Does God love it because it is pious or is it
pious because God loves it?
That question drives a wedge
between philosophy and religion, opening a gap that will never again be fully
closed. If what is right is right
because and only because God loves it, then justice begins and ends with
determining God’s will. This leads to something
like the Judaism of Yeshayahu
Leibowitz (1903–1994), who argued that an act can only be religious because
God commands it and for no other reason.
That an act is socially or medically beneficial is religiously irrelevant.
If, however, God loves the
pious because it is pious, then one can look for additional reasons why it is
pious. This leads in the direction of
philosophy and of course it is the route that Socrates takes.
I note that one can try to have
it both ways. That is the strategy
chosen by Thomas Aquinas. Some of God’s
law is valid only by revelation (remember the Sabbath Day) and some of His law
can be explained rationally (do not murder).
Thus philosophy becomes the handmaiden, if not the ally, of faith.
If the pious is loved by God
because it is pious, what makes it pious?
Socrates has to provide Euthyphro with a lot of help, but they agree
that pious is a kind of justice and justice is in general a kind of benefiting. When we take care of other people, that is a
form of justice in the ordinary sense.
When we tend to the requirements of the gods, that is pious proper. The problem here is that the gods are
presumably self-sufficient. They are,
after all immortal. To understand piety
as tending to the needs of the gods would mean that the gods are needy. That would imply imperfection and
defect. Neither Socrates nor his young
interlocutor are willing to accept this.
The dialogue ends with
Euthyphro’s exasperation. All I can tell
you, he tells Socrates, is that piety is serving the gods in a way that saves
cities and families. At that point, the
young man is out of steam and walks away from Socrates and the Porch of the
King. Socrates has successfully defended
the father.
Although the dialogue ends
without a decisive answer to the question, an answer is implied. We cannot understand why God or the gods care
about human beings or are concerned about what we do, if indeed we understand
the divine as Socrates did and as did the great Christian theologians. God is perfect. He cannot need us to do anything. We can however understand why we need the
gods. The ubiquitous presence of
religion in human history leaves no doubt that our turning to the divine is a
turn motivated by human neediness.
Scott
Atran has a piece in This View of Life that speaks to these issues. He is arguing with Sam Harris (a worthy cause).
Harris’s views on religion ignore the considerable progress
in cognitive studies on the subject over the last two decades, which show that
core religious beliefs do not have fixed propositional content (Atran
& Norenzayan, “Religion’s Evolutionary Landscape,” BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN
SCIENCES, 2004).
Indeed, religious beliefs, in being absurd (whether or not
they are recognized as such), cannot even be processed as comprehensible
because their semantic content is contradictory (for example, a bodiless but
physically powerful and sentient being, a deity that is one in three, etc).
It is precisely the ineffable nature of core religious
beliefs that accounts, in part, for their social and political adaptability
over time in helping to bond and sustain groups (Atran &
Ginges, “Religious and Sacred Imperatives in Human Conflict,” SCIENCE, 2012).
In fact, it is the ecstasy-provoking rituals that Harris describes as being
associated with such beliefs which renders them immune to the logical and
empirical scrutiny that ordinarily accompanies belief verification (see Atran &
Henrich, “The Evolution of Religion,” BIOLOGICAL THEORY, 2010).
This strikes me as largely
correct. It is precisely the
incomprehensible element in religious beliefs and doctrine that saves families
and cities, or as Atran puts it, helps “to bond and sustain groups.”
I would not endorse the term “absurd,”
however. If core religious beliefs lack
propositional content, that is based on a more or less conscious
proposition. What is proposed is that
world time (time, space, and comprehensible causation) is not a closed
system. The divine is something outside
the world of nameable, which is to say, rationally knowable things, something
that has an impact on that world. We can
nonetheless respond to that thing. That
is why God refuses to name Himself to the shoeless Moses.
This led Moses Maimonides to
conclude that the only theology possible is a negative theology. We cannot say anything about God except to
say what He is not. He is not mortal, not
limited in power…etc. Likewise, we
cannot understand why God loves the pious, but we cannot understand why we love
it. The abstract of Atran’s paper on “Religion’s
Evolutionary Landscape” is informative.
Religion is not an evolutionary adaptation per se, but a
recurring cultural by-product of the complex evolutionary landscape that sets
cognitive, emotional, and material conditions for ordinary human interactions.
Again, that strikes me as
correct. This does not in any way answer
the question whether the Kosmos is or is not a closed system, which is to say,
whether the Divine is real or not.
Instead, it recognizes the limits to human thinking. That, in itself, is a kind of piety.
No comments:
Post a Comment