Here is the third section of my paper on the evolution of virtue.
Aristotle’s account of virtue is rooted in his understanding of biology. He advanced a model of the human soul that was tripartite and hierarchical. According to this model, human beings share with all organisms a basic level of soul that he called vegetative. This level of soul includes such basic powers as feeding, growing, and producing waste. It opens up an existential dimension of value that extends from flourishing to decay and death.
Aristotle’s account of virtue is rooted in his understanding of biology. He advanced a model of the human soul that was tripartite and hierarchical. According to this model, human beings share with all organisms a basic level of soul that he called vegetative. This level of soul includes such basic powers as feeding, growing, and producing waste. It opens up an existential dimension of value that extends from flourishing to decay and death.
While
all animals share in the organic powers that make up vegetative soul, animals
have powers that plants do not have: motility and perception at a
distance. These powers open up a second
existential dimension: pain and pleasure.
Unlike plants, animals can have good and bad moments and good and bad
days.
Human
beings obviously share in all of this.
Just as obviously, we alone possess a third basic power: logos. Human beings are capable of speech and
reason. Logos makes it possible for us
to distinguish between what something looks like and how it really is. Most significant for moral thought, this
means we can distinguish between what looks good and bad and what is really
good and bad for us.
Aristotle’s
biology is unfortunately famous mostly for his howlers. He believed in spontaneous generation, for
example. Yet he got most of it
astonishingly right, according to modern evolutionary biology. His tripartite soul maps very well onto
evolutionary history. Evolution does not
work by adding new organisms to old ones built according to new
blueprints. Instead, it preserves what
works while piling new systems on top of the older ones. Some genes are unique to humans. Others, like the famous tool box genes, are
shared by all animals. One the three
basic systems that comprise the human brain is old enough to be called
reptilian. The neo-cortex, on the other
hand, seems primary only in the primates.
Aristotle
models the human soul in much the same way as his teacher Plato (or Plato’s
Socrates) did: by means of a political metaphor. One part of the human soul is distinctly
non-rational in so far as it does not respond to persuasion. This includes all the organic activities that
are rooted in the body and that are shared with other organisms. It includes the sensations, among which are
the pains and pleasures. Logos, by
contrast is uniquely human and its power is that of conscious thinking. In between is what we might call the middle
part of the soul. This part of the soul
includes the various passions. Each
passion includes an element of judgment: if I am angry, I am angry at someone
about something. Unlike the sensations
(let alone the unconscious organic processes) the passions are rational in so
far as they are susceptible to persuasion.
In the well-ordered human soul, reason rules the passions politically;
i.e. reason both commands and persuades them.
Reason and passion together rule the sensations royally or even
despotically, by command alone.
From
the viewpoint of evolutionary theory, the political metaphor is no mere
convenience. The passions develop their
rational dimension precisely because they develop in the course of our
evolution as political animals. To the
degree that human beings are capable of self-government, individually and
collectively, it is because the psychological capacities underlying
self-government were selected for. The
selection pressures that shaped these capacities were created by the advantages
that highly cooperative human associations enjoyed. Creatures capable of a sense of “we-ness” as
Michael Tomasello has put it, who have a sense of moral obligation that they
cannot easily escape, have largely inherited the earth. Precisely because human souls were not fashioned
anew but rather were built up out of preexisting psychological powers, it is
both possible and necessary for the more rational elements to govern the less
rational ones. The moral dimension is
one of the trajectories of our evolutionary history.
When
Aristotle looks for the nature of the virtues, he notes that there are three
things in this human soul. He is
focusing here on consciousness or mind as modern philosophy calls it. The three things are “feelings”, powers, and
dispositions. Under the first category,
he explicitly lists a number of passions, including desire, anger, fear, and
courage. The powers indicate the
capacity of the soul to generate the various feelings. We can certainly suppose that there are
creatures incapable of any of the feelings or only some and we can imagine that
we might have existed with a different emotional palette. By dispositions (or habits), he indicates
that fact that each person may be disposed to experience each of the passions
in an appropriate or inappropriate way.
Someone may be unable to feel sufficient anger when he has been
genuinely offended or feel more anger than is reasonable in any situation.
All
three of these categories fit well within the context of an evolutionary
analysis. The emotions that we feel
depend on an innate capacity to generate precisely this set of passionate
motives. Each emotive power exists in us
because it was selected for. In some set
of circumstances that reoccurred frequently over time the power to produce an
emotion contributed to the reproductive success of our ancestors. To take a single example, a capacity for
righteous indignation promoted cooperation by encouraging members of human
communities to punish or ostracize those who violate fundamental social
obligations. When we see such
violations, they look disgusting. There
is good evidence that the part of the brain that registers emotional disgust is
the same part of the brain that registers physical disgust, as for example what
we experience when we small rotting meat.
That is a good example of how evolution retools an existing emotive
power for a fundamentally new function.
To some
degree, our emotional dispositions are innate.
Some persons are innately more prone to anger or compassion that others
and men are in general more prone to violent aggression than are women. On the other hand, in all or almost all human
beings, the dispositions are flexible and subject to learning or
conditioning. Such flexibility makes
every kind of sense in an evolutionary context.
It allows human communities to adapt to a wide range of environmental
niches without having to suffer the losses that direct selection entails. Whereas a species of bacteria might respond
to a change in circumstances only after a catastrophic loss of numbers, a human
society might respond simply by changing the characteristic behavior of its
members. It also allows the community to
cultivate certain passions in certain ways, thus producing what we would call
moral culture. Finally, it allows an
individual to cultivate himself.
"So genes are unique to humans." Should probably be "Some genes . . ." And that's not entirely right, either. Even genes like the FOXP2 gene is shared by, say, chimpanzees -- the difference is the two mutations we have that chimpanzees do not. One would do better to look at the anatomical effects of the gene mutations. The giant fusiform cells that are found only in the great apes, or the fact that human's seem to be neotenous, which has an effect on gene expression timing.
ReplyDeleteTroy: thanks for the comment. You correct that the word should have been "some". I will give the rest of your comment some thought. I really like the example of the toolbox genes!
DeleteThis comment has been removed by a blog administrator.
ReplyDeleteNeurons are virtually indistinguishable among higher mammals: NPR.
ReplyDeleteLarry: interesting. I think it reinforces Aristotle's point. At a basic level, all organisms are the same.
ReplyDelete"There is good evidence that the part of the brain that registers emotional disgust is the same part of the brain that registers physical disgust."
ReplyDeleteThis is fascinating. Is it only true of disgust or are similar parts of the brain activated when we see a steak and when we see, say, Mother Theresa?
Miranda: If there is evidence of common brain area for appetizing things and admirable people, I do not know of it. As noted in a recent post, however, it seems likely that pro-social emotions are built atop the neural architecture of the parent-child bond. Those are very old and I suspect that they probably have little to do with appetite.
ReplyDeleteThat came out sounding a lot more Armin Miewesish than I had intended it to. I phrased it the way I did, because your statement led me to look up the spoiled meat, moral digust comparison link. I ended up reading an article that used reactions to Anthony Weiner and John Edwards as examples (http://science-report.net/article/brain-scans-show-morality-and-physical-disgust-closely-linked).
DeleteI used steak as an example, because it seemed like the opposite of spoiled meat and Mother Theresa because she seemed like the opposite of Anthony Weiner. In retrospect, that was probably a bad idea.
My question is not so much, "Do we think of moral people in the same way we think of tasty food?" It is, "Do our brains react to things we find morally appealing in the same way we react to things that are physically appealing?" Like steak. Or New York Bagels. Or is disgust unique? I will go back and re-read the parent-child bond post!