Austin Hughes has an
interesting piece in The New Atlantis:
“The
Folly of Scientism”. I think I will
have more to say about it later, but here I want to consider the difference
between philosophy and science.
Philosophy is the attempt to
become wise, that is, to replace opinions about the most important things with
knowledge about those things. The most
important things fall generally into two classes of questions or topics. Human beings want to know what the nature of
the world is and what their place is in that world. This desire is not directly related to any
practical concern. We just want to know,
or at least have something we can take for granted. We also want to know how to live in this
world.
These two questions find their
most famous expression in the two creation stories with which the book of
genesis begins. The first creation story
lays out the order of creation. The
second explains why human existence is difficult and points to the solution for
the difficulty in getting right with God.
Most human beings rely on such
received stories, supplemented by experience, to satisfy the craving for
answers to these two questions. The
distinction between opinions and knowledge, however, drives the philosopher to
attempt to answer them by a single method: relentless questioning. The philosopher attempts to achieve wisdom by
asking one question after another until, hopefully all questions have been
answered. That no philosopher has yet
managed to achieve that goal explains why philosophy continues to this
day.
Unlike religion and mythology,
philosophy is not ubiquitous. It begins
in specific place and time (Asia Minor in the sixth century BC). All subsequent philosophy seems to depend on
contact with the tradition that began there.
This is not to disparage other traditions of thought; it is simply to
recognize the one that gave birth to modern science
Socrates encountered philosophy
as an ongoing practice. His student
Plato found it necessary to devote each dialogue to a distinct set of
questions. Aristotle further refines the
distinctions by establishing distinct lines of inquiry for his various
books. Each book begins with certain
questionable assumptions and proceeds on the basis of those assumptions. For example, his Physics begins with the assumption that various natural things
exist‑growing plants and moving spheres.
With that procedure‑putting aside more general questions to focus on
more specific ones‑science is born.
All science follows that
general pattern. One way to move toward
a comprehensive knowledge of the Kosmos is to try to understand the various
parts of the Kosmos. Modern science
follows suit but adds a new requirement for science that Aristotle did
not. It insists on articulating the
questions in such a way that the mode of answering the question is implicit. This is what is meant by the phrase “a
testable hypothesis” and any genuinely scientific hypothesis hast to meet that
criterion. The power of that addition to
the concept of science is evident to anyone who appreciates modern
science.
“Scientism” is a pejorative
term for the claim that modern science can answer all questions and that it is
the sole standard for the truth of any belief or proposition. I am not at all certain that this term is
useful. If you think that more is being
claimed on behalf of modern science that it warranted or that science has over
stepped its proper bounds, it is enough to demand a testable hypothesis.
Much of contemporary science
looks a lot more like classical than like modern science. For example, what explains the phenomenon of
homosexuality? David
P. Barash comments on this biological mystery in The Chronicle. Contemporary
research programs offer only marginal findings.
All we can do is list the prospective explanations and consider the
strengths and weaknesses of each. That
is pretty much how Aristotle proceeded.
No comments:
Post a Comment