While reading Nagel’s proposal for a
more complete, trans-physical account of nature, it occurs to me that the
mind/body problem doesn’t seem to appear in Aristotle’s work at all. To be sure, Aristotle was a vehement
anti-reductionist. This is especially
evident in his remarks on Empedocles.
The latter argued that the curvature of the spine is a result of the
confinement of the fetus in the womb, which is the kind of thing you have to
argue if you want to maximize the role of chance in all physical
explanations. Aristotle rightly supposed
that such features of anatomy have a species-cause.
By contrast, Aristotle saw no
tension at all between materialist and mechanical explanations, on the one
hand, and formal and teleological explanations on the other. Consider his famous account of the four
causes. Here is the translation from my
old Charlton edition of the first two books of the Physics.
[1] According to one way of speaking, that out of which as a
constituent a thing comes to be is called a cause; for example, the bronze and
the silver and their genera would be the cause respectively of a statue and a
loving cup. [2] According to another,
the form or model is a cause; this is the account of what the being would be,
and its genera‑thus the cause of an octave is the ratio of two to one, and more
generally number‑and the parts which come into the account. [3] Again, there is the primary source of
change or the staying unchanged: for example, the man who has deliberated is a
cause, the father is the cause of the child, and in general that which makes
something of that which is made, and that which changes something of that which
is changed. [4] And again a thing may be
a cause as the end. That is what
something is for, as health might be what a walk is for. On account of what does he walk? We answer ‘To keep fit’ and think that, in
saying that, we have given the cause.
Cause here translates aitia, a word that philosophy borrowed
from forensic language. It originally
meant responsibility, as in who done it.
In Aristotle’s work, it implies an answer to a certain kind of
question.
Aristotle provides helpful
examples in each case, but I will expand one of his examples to cover all four
cases. Consider the development of a
human being from conception to birth.
How does one explain this process?
One obvious answer is that the developing person comes to be out of
certain kinds of material, which the scholarship refers to as material
causation. Another answer is that the
human being comes to be because the developing being is human in species. This is formal causation. A third answer is that Da knew Ma and got
things rolling. That is efficient
causation. Finally, the developing being
develops toward a predetermined end, according to a program that was present at
the very beginning. That is final
causation.
I think that this is dead spot
on. An organism, human or otherwise,
comes to be because it comes to be out of certain kinds of material, just as a functioning
machine is an arrangement of materials moving and changing in certain
ways. I doubt that there is anything
going on in a human body or mind that does not have a material substratum.
An organism comes to be from
existing organisms of the same species.
Cats give birth to cats and never to catfish. Aristotle recognized that the species form
had to exist in two versions: the expressed organism (what we would call the
phenotype) and the implicit form transmitted in the act of conception (the genotype). Aristotle thought that the latter was
introduced by the father, whereas the mother supplied only the matter. We know better, but it doesn’t change the
general scheme.
Efficient causation is what
happens when an existing system is destabilized from outside. The father destabilizes the mother by
introducing his semen. However, in the
case of a developing organism, the force of efficient causation does not
scatter like billiard balls. Instead, it
gathers toward a predetermined end, guided by the species form. Final or teleological causation is an obvious
fact of ontogeny.
Aristotle’s four causes make up
a correct and comprehensive set of biological explanations. What is striking, from the viewpoint of
contemporary philosophy, is that he didn’t see any conflict between material and
efficient causation (which modern physical science has long wanted to rely on
exclusively) and formal and final causation.
He wasn’t the least bit worried about reducing the latter to the former
nor did he desire it.
I suspect that one of the
reasons for this is that Aristotle begins with biology. While his writing aims at a comprehensive
account of nature, his preoccupied with animals. Modern science is beginning to come around to
Aristotle’s way of thinking, through no fault of its own. The long dominion of physics, which began
with the advent of modern science, is probably at an end. Biology is the most important of modern
sciences just now, and that is good for science. It may be that living organisms have more to
teach us than anything else in the visible Kosmos.
No comments:
Post a Comment