I was called on a point recently
by a colleague. He accused me of jumping
between two irreconcilable positions. One
the one hand, I argued that human beings are distinct from other animals in
kind and not merely in degree (i.e., just more intelligent). On the other hand, I argued that traces of
human intelligence and moral capacity are found in animals. I replied that I’m a primate; jumping from
one tree to another is what I do. It got
a laugh.
I don’t think I was actually
guilty of a contradiction. Traces of
language are indeed found in animals. A
certain call may indicate food or danger.
Yet, so far as we know, no other animal is capable of drawing and
recognizing a simple symbol like a stick man.
Differences in kind do not require altogether novel capacities. They require that something about the way a
capacity is exercised be novel.
Today I have been looking at two
studies of logically moral behavior among non-human animals. Vampire bats have long served as poster
children for reciprocal altruism. These
winged mammals feed exclusively on blood.
They need to feed about once every three days. This presents a challenge as their food
sources have legs and can move in unpredictable ways.
The vampires deal with this
problem by blood sharing. A bat who
returns hungry can count on a share of a meal from a luckier roost mate. This is an insurance policy; however, it
invites cheating. An unscrupulous bat might
take from others and then refused to share.
If he gets away with that, his offspring will proliferate and the
sharing system will collapse.
That requires an enforcement
mechanism. Vampires remember. If bat X refuses to share with me today, I will
refuse to share with bat X tomorrow.
Cheaters can be systematically eliminated from the gene pool.
I doubt that bats are consciously
moral. I am sure that this sharing
system is logically moral. Bat X either
fulfills his obligations or does not. If
so, he benefits from the social contract.
If not, then he is excluded from the contract.
I used this example in the paper
I am writing for the APSA this year. I
wanted to be sure that recent scholarship backed up this account, and it
does. Gerald G. Carter and Gerald S.
Wilkinson have a piece in the Proceedings of the Royal Society (2013). They teased apart alternative explanations
for the vampire’s behavior.
Are the bats sharing only because
they are related to one another? If so,
then kin selection and not reciprocal altruism would explain their
behavior. In the experiment, relatedness
was the least reliable predictor of one bat’s willingness to share with
another.
Perhaps sharing was a response to
allogrooming. Bats share with cuddle buddies. Perhaps it was influenced by mating agendas: if
I share with her, she will mate with me.
Those were the third and second-best predictors of sharing
behavior.
The best predictor was simply
that the other bat had shared in the past.
That looks like reciprocal
altruism. Sharing is rewarded with
sharing. Remembering who is a good
partner amounts to the construction of a social network.
The most interesting thing to
come out of this study is this: sharing was often initiated not by the hungry
bat but by the sated bat. Why would this
be so? Sharing builds a network of
obligations. If I can get you to accept
my donation, you are now obligated to me.
This system is, as the sociologists say, socially constructed. It depends on reputation, what the other bats
think about this one.
Something of the same kind is
going on in a study of cleaner fish.
These fish make their living eating parasites in the jaws, gills, etc.,
of larger predators. As in the case of
the vampire bats, this arrangement involves mutual obligations and the
temptation to cheat. Client predators
can cheat by gobbling up the cleaner after the work is finished. That is policed by a simple accounting. A predator who behaves that way will discover
that the cleaners no longer come out of their cleaner stations when he swims in
for a touch up.
Cleaner fish are also tempted to
cheat. The parasites they feed on are
not quite as attractive as the mucus in the client’s jaws. What encourages the cleaner to confine itself
to the parasites? Russel D. Fernald
explains this in his note Animal Cooperation: Keeping a Clean(ing) Reputation
[Current Biology Vol. 21 No 13].
It turns out that cleaner wrasses
are more likely to keep honest (parasites only) when they are observed by a
number of potential client fish. They
seem to value their reputation in the business.
It seems very unlikely that these fish, with their tiny brains, have any
conscious awareness of the stakes. It
doesn’t matter. Natural selection has
made the logically moral choices for them.
Again, the reciprocal arrangement
is socially constructed. The fish do not
need to understand the system, but they do need to notice who is watching.
The old dichotomy between nature and
nurture, biological influence and social construction, is long out of
date. Temperature, saltiness, water and
nutrients are factors that exert selection pressure on organisms. Social arrangements and the likes and
dislikes of individual interactors for one another also exert select
pressure.
Choice is a powerful influence on
the evolution of pretty much everything.
Another powerful influence is moral logic. Plato was right, at least about the world of
living organisms. The most important
idea is the idea of the good.
No comments:
Post a Comment