I confess that I did not know,
until tonight, that Aristotle understood precisely what a lunar eclipse
is. This is rather significant, because
I had generally assumed that Aristotle’s physics was entirely
indefensible. While I am now on solid
ground in holding that is biology is mostly solid ground, what of his view that
a pitched falls back to earth because its earthy nature compels it to return to
its natural place? Aristotle did not
have a reliable theory of momentum. But
then I came across this passage in the Posterior
Analytics.
τί ἐστιν ἔκλειψις; στέρησις φωτὸς
ἀπὸ σελήνης
ὐπὸ γῆς
ἀντιφραξεως.
Pretty straight forward, no? Here it is in English.
What is an eclipse? A deprivation
of light against the moon due to the obstruction of the earth.
That is dead spot on, which is
astonishing for his time. He even goes
on to say that this explanation, which relies on speculation, would be directly
apparent if we were standing on the moon.
We would see the earth moving across the sun. I am not going to try to rehabilitate
Aristotle’s astronomy; however, I can’t help pointing out that, in considering
the same event from two different points in space, he is perilously close here
not only to Newton but to Einstein.
I was reading the PA because I
read a very fine paper by Lucas Mix: “Nested explanations in Aristotle and Mayr,”
in Synthese (2016) 193: 1817-1832, and Mariska Leunissen’s book Explanation and Teleology in Aristotle’s
Science of Nature. Leunissen points
out that Aristotle’s explanatory strategies may help us resolve certain
fundamental problems in the modern philosophy of biology. This is what Mix tries to do in joining
Aristotle with Ernst Mayr, two of my favorite philosophers of biology.
Modern biology involves a host of
evolutionary and organismal explanations that cannot be generated by physics and
chemistry alone. Chemistry can tell you
a lot about the DNA molecules but it cannot explain what a gene is, let alone
make sense of organisms, adaptation, end-directed processes, etc. At the same time, all biological phenomena
depend on the mechanical laws of physics.
All organic activities, from metabolism to mental gymnastics require the
expenditure of energy and fail when the energy runs out; yet only organisms can
succeed or fail at anything. How are we
to understand the relationship between these two domains of science?
Here is how Mix puts it:
Nested explanations provide the most utility for biology. Good
evolutionary explanations involve natural selection acting on replicating
physical systems; therefore, the fullest biological knowledge will appeal to an
evolutionary explanation nested within a mechanical explanation (or series of
explanations). The evolutionary explanation is etiologically prior; it defines
the categories in question (functions, organisms, genes). The mechanical
explanation is temporally prior; it includes the material from which they are
made and the rules by which they interact.
To say that evolutionary
explanations are nested with mechanical explanations is to say they are a very
special case of mechanical explanations.
Some physical systems have nothing to do with the former, as in the case
of volcanoes. Other physical systems
like redwood trees cannot be understood without the former. To say that the evolutionary explanation is
etiologically prior to the mechanical explanation is to say that one must
approach the study of living organisms with a basic understanding of what they
are and that this is something that mechanical explanations cannot
provide.
Here is my take, for which Mix
bears no responsibility. The relationship
between the mechanistic sciences, which ask only how something happened or is what it is, and the life sciences,
which ask why something happened or why it is as it is, is analogous to the
relationship between the Oxford English dictionary and a good English grammar,
on the one hand, and Shakespeare’s Richard the Third on the other hand.
Ignoring poetic license for the
moment, Shakespeare was limited to a specific number of letters, a large but
finite vocabulary, a large but finite number of grammatical rules, as well as a
brevity dictated by the realities of the stage.
Given those restraints, an astronomically vast but finite number of
plays was possible. If you don’t believe
me, read Jorge Luis Borges’ famous story, “The Library of Babel.” It’s a good but sad joke to say that all one
needs is a dictionary because all the other books are in it. To get Dickey Three out of the OED, among the
vast alternative populations, you need Shakespeare.
To get William Shakespeare out of
the vast possibilities that the physical kosmos offers, you need what? It is hardly clear. We have no good idea how life arose out of
the chemical soups, sunlight, and lightening scoured landscapes that the earth
offered just before it began to fruit.
Fruit it did, and the playwright known as natural selection has been scribbling
furiously ever since.
Just as an interpreter of
Shakespeare must begin with the play and not the dictionary, so a biologist
must begin with living organisms and not with the periodic table of
elements. Organic chemistry is organic
first and chemical second. Of course
here the analogy breaks down. The
dictionary doesn’t tell you much about the play. Chemistry and physics tell you a lot about
living organisms. Why are there a lot of
animals here and not so many there?
Sunlight and temperature tell you a lot about why there are trees with
certain kinds of leaves and that tells you why there are a lot of creates that
eat the leaves and predators that eat the leaf eaters.
I like the notion of nested
explanations because it seems to reflect the most basic human reality. We are nested within the biosphere on the
surface of this planet. We thrive on
certain geographies and not so much or at all on others. The biosphere is also nested in a larger
range, but still only a sliver of the world.
Outside, there is the too cold or too hot and the empty silence.
As Mix observes, Aristotle was
good at nesting one kind of explanation within another. He saw no contradiction between material and
mechanistic causation, on the one hand, and the power of organic forms and
teleological processes on the other. He
might have been the last great philosopher to be altogether comfortable with all
the ways that science could offer for understand the physical and existential realities of our life on this world. I
must admit that I am a little uncomfortable with that.
Discomfort drives the history of
philosophy and science. Still, both must
continue to pursue the final view that will integrate and resolve all the
problems. Just right now, I am feeling
some of Aristotle’s confidence.
No comments:
Post a Comment