I was educated in a hotbed of
Western Straussians led by the hero of that school, Harry Jaffa. No idea so roused our temper as the infamous “fact-value
dichotomy.” This is the idea that
statements of fact (e.g., electricity can kill people) are fundamentally
different from statements of value (e.g., it was wrong to electrocute Julius
and Ethel Rosenberg). The former are
either true or false and one can attempt to tell which is which by means of argument
and evidence. The latter can be judged
as true or false only in so far as they are logically consistent with other
value judgments (e.g., it is wrong to kill as a punishment for a crime). All such logical analysis, however, can only
link one value judgment to another and must ultimately come to rest in some
basic value (human life is sacred, etc.).
Such basic values can be held but they cannot be argued for nor is there
any evidence that would tell for or against them. The fact-value dichotomy seems to reduce moral
judgements to irrational beliefs. To
believe in genuine justice is like believing in fairies.
For Strauss, and especially for
the Western Straussians, this amounted to offense against all moral and
political philosophy. Why think
carefully about what justice is or what a just political order would be, as
Plato and Aristotle did, if justice is just some idea that can never amount to
anything more than an idea one is fond of without reason? On the contrary, we argued, Socrates in Plato’s
Republic and Gorgias offers profound arguments in favor of a coherent account of
justice and his account is solidly based in evidence and logic. Moreover, Socrates derives his logical proofs
precisely from the testimony of those who argue against the existence or at
least the worth of justice.
The fact-value dichotomy is
usually traced back to David Hume’s discussion of the naturalistic
fallacy. One cannot derive an ought-statement,
which describes what one should or should not do, from an is-statement, which
describes some set of facts. For
example, one cannot derive the claim “Athens shouldn’t have made Socrates drink
hemlock” from the claim that “hemlock is poisonous.” One can only derive the former from some
other ought-statement such as: “you shouldn’t execute good men who will later
be both famous and popular”.
For a long time I thought that
Hume’s distinction was silly. I thought
one could easily derive the claim that “one ought not to stick one’s tongue in
a light socket” from the claim that “the socket is turned on”. I now regard that thought as naïve and
apologize to Mr. Hume.
This occurred to me as I have
been teaching logic and yesterday began a section on moral logic. I have also been (belatedly) revising my
chapter for The Handbook of Biology and
Politics. Both of these activities
directed my attention to this question.
Modern logic generally accepts the naturalistic fallacy as a fallacy and
hence presents coherent moral arguments as resting on two sorts of claim. At least one premise of the argument must
state some set of facts and another premise must state some value
judgement. For example:
- Current carbon emissions are causing global warming and global warming will have dangerous consequences for human beings and other creatures.
- One ought not to do things that are dangerous to human beings and other creatures.
- Therefore: we ought to reduce our carbon emissions.
I think that the distinction
between these two types of statements is logically correct, but I would point
out two things that are frequently overlooked in discussion of facts and
values.
The first is that the category of
values includes not only moral judgments but all judgments involving such
concepts as right and wrong, better or worse, etc. Thus “I shouldn’t eat what is unhealthy” is
as much a value judgment as “I shouldn’t steal candy from a baby.” What I and my Straussian friends and teachers
objected to was the claim that moral
judgments were in effect irrational.
Including value judgments about self-interest tells against that
claim. There is nothing irrational about
ought-statements when they apply to matters of health. For the same reason, there is nothing
necessarily irrational about such statements when they apply to matters of
right and wrong.
My second point is more
important. The real distinction here is
not between facts and values but facts about the living and the dead. Recently I watched a NOVA feature on North
America. In the second segment we were
presented with a line drawn along a hill side in the North Dakota Badlands,
which I know well. The line represented
evidence of an asteroid strike. Below
the line (earlier in time) one finds dinosaur bones. Above the line one finds fossils, but no
dinosaurs. Conclusion: the asteroid strike
killed off the dinosaurs. This kind of
analysis is all facts and no values. The
reason for that is that, whatever killed the off, the dinosaurs are just plain
dead. Fossils are not more involved in
values that volcanic rock.
By contrast, living animals,
including human beings, always have something at stake. They are subject to flourishing and
withering, surviving and perishing. That
includes all of them, from the giant popular tree I walked around in Joyce
Kilmer Memorial Forest, down to the littlest bacterium. Some organisms are also subject to pain and
pleasure. That includes all (or perhaps
almost all) of the animals. One species
is capable of happiness, defined as a self-conscious appreciation of a satisfying
life. Value judgments, far from being
products of human culture, or “social construction”, or irrational emotive
artifacts, are simple features of organic life.
Every time a slime mold amoeba decides to congregate with its fellows or
a snow leopard turns down a trail to follow a scent, a value judgment is
made. Since such efforts can succeed for
fail, value judgments can be objectively true or false.
Aristotle that to understand
simple things one must recognize a number of irreducible dimensions. To understand how a table can be both wide
and narrow, taller than a chair but shorter than the kitchen wall, one must
recognize that width cannot be reduced to length nor to height. The world exists in a three dimensional
space. To understand organic life, one
must recognize the dimension of value.
Unlike rocks, house plants, horses, and human beings can succeed or
fail. The latter two have good days and
bad.
Moral arguments require value
judgments as premises for the same reason that arguments about individual and
collective interests do. If you can’t
reduce an is to an ought, that is because human beings are
not rocks. It is nonetheless true that
slavery requires telling lies about the slaves and the masters and that tyranny
is bad for human beings in general.
Moral and political philosophy is viable because it recognizes facts
about human nature.