Sitting at a table in a Chinese
restaurant in San Francisco, I was asked how it is possible for an ape to
pray? This was a direct challenge to my
interest in evolutionary explanations for human political and moral behavior.
I responded that a wide range
of animals have two sets of limbs, fore and aft, and that in one species of ape
the pads of the forelimbs can be brought together in front of the chest. I was being facetious, of course; but not
altogether facetious. Prayer often
involves physical activity and such activities are both enabled and constrained
by biological facts.
I went on to suggest that the
same is true of the spiritual activities involved in prayer. Like most animals, human beings have an
evolved capacity to infer what is invisible from what is visible. When a polar bear is hunting, it does not
look for anything that looks like a seal.
It looks for mist coming from a hole in the ice. A human hunter tracking prey looks first not
for the animal itself but for signs of its passing and course.
Unlike all other animals, the
human ape has a robust capacity for forming a theory of mind. This means that I understand that other
people and other animals have minds like I do and I can use this fact to
predict their behavior and engage with them.
This capacity underwrites both our social lives and our animal
husbandry.
Inclined by our evolved
capacities to look for signs of what is invisible and to infer intentions and
will behind visible behavior, it is not difficult to understand how this ape learned to pray. Of course, these instincts can lead to
mistakes. The erupting volcano is not
really angry nor do the entrails of the bird really indicate the will of the gods. Or so I suppose.
However, that does not mean
that prayer is always or even mostly a mistake.
All prayer is a turning of the human mind toward the divine. In that sense it is like treasure hunting,
which can be understood regardless of whether there is treasure underneath the
X. Understanding how our evolved
inclinations make prayer possible and how they influence its expressions cannot
tell us whether the object of that turning exists or what its character
is. Such an understanding certainly does
not allow us to infer that the treasure does not exist.
Steven Pinker has a piece
in The New Republic attacking the critics of “scientism”. This is a pejorative term meaning in general
the idea that science can explain everything and (always) in particular, the
idea that science can explain something the critic does not want science to
explain. The term is typically deployed
against those who inquire into the evolutionary and developmental roots of
human culture.
Pinker thinks that science and
the humanities are not at odds with one another. He makes a strong case and one with which I
am largely in agreement. To add my own
two cents, evolutionary science can tell you a lot about why Romeo and Juliet
were attracted to one another. It can
tell you a lot about why we love such stories.
Human beings are sexually reproducing creatures. Our mating behavior is extraordinarily rich
in the psychological depth of our displays and motives. Each of us is interested, obviously, in our
own loves and lusts and (almost as obviously) in those involved in third party
arrangements. Our interest in Romeo and
Juliet is intelligible.
Pinker draws a useful distinct
between intelligibility and reductionism.
Demonizers of scientism often confuse intelligibility with a
sin called reductionism. But to explain a complex happening in terms of deeper
principles is not to discard its richness. No sane thinker would try to explain
World War I in the language of physics, chemistry, and biology as opposed to
the more perspicuous language of the perceptions and goals of leaders in 1914
Europe. At the same time, a curious person can legitimately ask why human minds
are apt to have such perceptions and goals, including the tribalism,
overconfidence, and sense of honor that fell into a deadly combination at that
historical moment.
Yes. The laws of physics, chemistry, and biology
were in full force when a bullet pierced the shirt of the Archduke
Ferdinand. If biology has something to
offer here, it is because biology has principles that are not derivable from
chemistry and physics. Likewise,
historical analysis must determine factors (chance and culture) that are not derivable
from biology.
While Pinker thinks that
science and the humanities are not at odds with one another, he clearly does
think that science rules out certain ways of thinking about the human
things.
The moral worldview of any scientifically literate
person—one who is not blinkered by fundamentalism—requires a radical break from
religious conceptions of meaning and value.
To begin with, the findings of science entail that the
belief systems of all the world’s traditional religions and cultures—their
theories of the origins of life, humans, and societies—are factually mistaken.
We know, but our ancestors did not, that humans belong to a single species of
African primate that developed agriculture, government, and writing late in its
history. We know that our species is a tiny twig of a genealogical tree that
embraces all living things and that emerged from prebiotic chemicals almost
four billion years ago. We know that we live on a planet that revolves around
one of a hundred billion stars in our galaxy, which is one of a hundred billion
galaxies in a 13.8-billion-year-old universe, possibly one of a vast number of
universes. We know that our intuitions about space, time, matter, and causation
are incommensurable with the nature of reality on scales that are very large
and very small. We know that the laws governing the physical world (including
accidents, disease, and other misfortunes) have no goals that pertain to human
well-being. There is no such thing as fate, providence, karma, spells, curses,
augury, divine retribution, or answered prayers—though the discrepancy between
the laws of probability and the workings of cognition may explain why people
believe there are. And we know that we did not always know these things, that
the beloved convictions of every time and culture may be decisively falsified,
doubtless including some we hold today.
I happen to believe most of
what Pinker states in that passage, but I am pretty sure that I do not know any
of it and neither does he. I am very dubious
about “spells, curses, [and] augury” but I cannot think of what science I can
rely on to rule out “fate, providence, karma, divine retribution, or answered
prayers”. In fact, I know that such things cannot be ruled
out because that would depend on assumptions that science requires but cannot
establish. Science assumes uniformity in
physical laws both across space and time, for which reason it rules out
miracles. Such an assumption is very
useful and indeed very powerful; however, it is still just an assumption. It cannot be verified by scientific reasoning
since the latter requires it. If there
were, indeed, an omnipotent God, outside of time and space (an alternative
assumption) then quite literally everything goes.
Still, it was right for Pinker
to issue this challenge. It is quite
true that science is not the enemy of the humanities. I would go further to say that it is not the
enemy of religion either. This does not
mean that is rests comfortably with either.
Science should make us uncomfortable.
Leo Strauss argued that one of
the great sources of vitality in Western Civilization is the conflict between
reason and revelation. From the time of
Thomas Aquinas, to be sure, intelligent persons have had to wrestle with two
claims to wisdom. While I think that
Pinker is right to push the claims of science as authoritative, I am also
grateful for the honorable opposition. All
science is just a special case of philosophy.
Philosophy is rooted in the knowledge of what one does not know. Without religion, who would continue to
remind those of a scientific mind that they do not know what they think they
know?
Perhaps an ape who has learned how to put the pads of his forelimbs together - or maybe a rival scientific mind - or possibly even God himself.
ReplyDeleteOr perhaps a shrewd commenter on a blog. But I suppose that the categories are not mutually exclusive.
ReplyDeleteI agree. On a more serious note - why should science make people uncomfortable?
ReplyDeleteMiranda: this is a very serious question and goes to the heart of the tension between philosophy/science and politics that was the context of every Platonic dialogue.
ReplyDeleteI answer that philosophy in general and science in a more specific way are attempts to replace opinions about important things with knowledge. Opinions (which are nothing more than points of view) are what guides most of us (maybe everyone except Socrates). They guide us and provide satisfying answers to basic questions. We often cherish our opinions, not only because they provide such guidance but because they comfort us.
For that reason alone, any questioning of our opinions is likely to make us at least a bit uncomfortable. It is entirely possible, of course, that we may come to know exactly what we now opine. Someone who believes that the world is more or less round because he has been told that it is and is comfortable with that image may discover, once he has been asked to explain why that belief is correct, that the world is in fact round. On the other hand, someone who is satisfied with the view that the world was created in six days (over, perhaps, six thousand years) may find out that his comfortable belief was false. Regardless of how it turns out, the first genuine questioning is likely to make one uneasy.
Some years ago I listened to a discussion of student rights in the classroom. Students have a right to be treated in a certain way, fairly and impartially, for example. Does a professor transgress when he challenges the student in such a way as to make her or him uncomfortable? Some of those in the room seemed to think so. I raised my hand and remarked that anyone who gets through four years of college without once being made uncomfortable in a classroom should sue for malpractice.