Two perennial and obviously
closely related questions in the biosocial sciences are whether human beings
are violent by nature and whether our close relatives among the great apes are
violent by nature. It is obvious that
human beings and chimpanzees display violent behavior in fact, both within
groups (politics) and between groups (war).
For those inclined to believe that such violence is not the produce of
evolution but instead a result of unnatural environmental factors (which is to
say, factors that did not constitute substantial selection pressures during
their evolution), there are a number of available arguments.
One is that the last twelve
thousand years have seen the rise of social conditions among human beings that
are very different from those in which any primate ever lived before. Large surpluses and the social stratification
that was made possible by those surpluses gave human beings something to fight
about. That is the most plausible case
for the thesis that violence is accidental rather than natural to our species. It flies in the face of evidence that human
beings were more violent in hunter-gatherer societies that approximate the
environment of evolutionary adaptation.
A second argument is that human
beings are largely responsible for chimpanzee violence. Humans have put enormous stress on
chimpanzees (by restricting their foraging ranges, etc.) and this, not their
nature, is to blame. For a third
argument, one may look to our other cousins, the bonobos. These animals do not fight wars, organize
hunts, or display much interpersonal violence in their groups.
To make the bonobo argument
plausible, one would have to explain why the same artificial pressures that
make chimpanzees violent have not had the same effect on bonobos. If it has, I have not seen it reported. The absence of violence among bonobos is
thought to result from the power of female coalitions. These coalitions are built upon networks of
sexual partnerships among the females and function to protect the sons of the
coalition partners.
The problem with using bonobos to
argue that the three species are not inherently violent is that is raises the
question of what the female coalitions arose to do in the first place. Mothers collective protect their sons, which
they would not have to do if their sons did not need protection. That this has been going on for long enough
to modify the bonobo’s evolution is evident from the fact that bonobo males are
considerably smaller and less robust than chimpanzee males.
Competition for status among
males is less intense and largely nonviolent but it is not absent. Males who have living mothers are apparently
advantaged in status competition over motherless males. Motherless males are also subject to much
more aggression by other males, especially when they are young. It appears that bonobos are the exception
that proves the rule. Their tendencies
to interpersonal violence are not absent, they are merely suppressed by a
special feature of pan paniscus evolution.
As for chimpanzees, a
study published in Nature does short work with the excuses for violence in
this species. From a summary in The Washington Post:
The paper, which analyzed data from 426 combined years of
observation and 18 separate chimp sites, argues chimps are not driven to
violence by their contacts with humans, which some scientists have previously
contended. Chimps, rather, are natural born killers.
“Variation in killing rates was unrelated to measures of human
impacts,” said
the paper, which was researched by an international team of 30 scientists. “…
The adaptive strategies hypothesis views killing as an evolved tactic by which
killers tend to increase their fitness through increased access to territory,
food, mates and other benefits.”
The research feeds into a lengthy debate over the nature of
chimp violence, and what it means for humanity’s own propensity for murder.
“We’re trying to make inferences about human evolution,” lead researcher
Michael L. Wilson, an anthropologist at the University of Minnesota, told
the New York Times. Even in areas where humanity’s hand and habitat loss were
not discernible, the chimps conveyed the same bellicosity, the research found.
It signified that competition over resources— even when abundant — drove
the chimp wars.
So if chimpanzees are not less
violent where human influences are not felt and resources are abundant and
bonobos are not more violent where human influences cause stress, then it seems
clear that pan troglodyte is in fact violent by nature and bonobos not. If bonobos are less violent not because aggressive
tendencies are absent but because they have been suppressed by another
evolutionary adaptation, then it seems likely that the tendencies toward
violent aggression have been inherited by both species from their common pan
ancestors. Finally, if human beings were
more troglodyte in behavior than paniscus in their behavior before the rise of
settled agriculture, then it seems likely that the history of violence
stretches back to the common ancestors of all three species.
This has significant implications
for political philosophy. Jean Jacques
Rousseau argued precisely that human beings were asocial and therefore
non-aggressive by nature. It was only a
terrible accident of history that drove human beings together and created the
conditions for inequality and violence.
Rousseau was wrong.
Thomas Hobbes argued not that
human beings were violent by nature but that the logic of their situation when
they meet drives them in the direction of violence. I might get what I want by killing you and
you, knowing this, have an incentive to kill me first. Hobbes was closer to the truth, but failed to
consider that such logic would have to be partially built-in to be
effective. The context works by
triggering instincts. If our instincts
were not Hobbesian, neither would be our behavior.
John Locke supposed that what
really made us dangerous was our inherent sense of justice. Our tendency to invoke the executive power
that belongs to everyone by nature can make really enemies out of human
parties, each of which thinks it has been wronged by the other. Locke was pretty much dead spot on. Our moral instincts are built upon the
political and territorial instincts of our ape (or proto-ape) ancestors.
All three of these early modern
philosophers were, however, proceeding on the basis of a big mistake. They supposed that man is by nature an
isolated animal. Not only political
institutions but all human societies are largely accidental. As the nature of a wall does not change much
the nature of bricks, so what is natural to us is only what we bring to any
society of which be become a part.
Aristotle did not make that
mistake. Just as a biologist cannot
recognize a gene except by recognizing the function it has in the cellular
machinery, so we cannot understand the nature of a single human being except by
recognizing how he or she shapes and is shaped by social and indeed moral and
political communities. It remains the
fact that we do carry with us a nature that contains our evolutionary history
within it. The three homo species (to
use a proposed and, I think, correct specification) carry with them a history
of violence.